Dewey,
Gadamer and the Status of Poetry Among the Arts
When
Alcuin argued for the artes liberales in the Carolingian court, three things kept poetry from
finding a distinctive place: Plato's concerns about the corruptive power of
poetry; poesis—"making"—suggesting
poetry belonged to the mechanical rather than liberal arts; and the Pythagorean
mathematicization of music. Through the middle ages, the best poetry could hope
for was a place under the category of rhetoric; though, since it was then seen
as oriented only to pleasure, the Medieval Church shared Plato's suspicions.
So, when poetry took off in the 14th century it's not surprising
that something so connected to both language and music should seem to transcend
the split between the trivium
(grammar, rhetoric, and logic) and quadrivium (arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and
music). When Leonardo da Vinci in 1490 argued that painting not only belongs
among the liberal arts, but is the highest of the arts, it was music and
poetry—one the master of invisible things, the other the master of
visible things—he sought to dethrone. Poetry was no longer a tool of
rhetoric, but an art of first rank, and the nature of music lie in its
emotional power, not in mathematical relations.
Leonardo's
arguments never caught on, but the link between poetry and music has been often
repeated, as has been their status as the highest of the arts. In the 19th
century G.F.W. Hegel called poetry "the universal art of the mind."[1]
It "runs though all the arts" and is art's "highest phase," one phase higher
than music. Arthur Schopenhauer inverted the priority: poetry is "the true
mirror of the real nature of the world and life,"[2] but music, since it speaks directly to
the will unmediated by ideas, is the "most powerful of all the arts."[3]
A young John Dewey wrote "The various fine arts, architecture, sculpture,
painting, music and poetry are the successive attempts of the mind to
adequately express its own ideal nature, or, more correctly stated, adequately
to produce that which will satisfy its own demands for a love of a perfectly
harmonious nature, something in which admiration may rest."[4]
The ordering of the arts is not accidental; poetry is above music, especially
dramatic poetry, as it "consummatesÉthe range of fine arts, because in dramatic
form we have the highest ideal of self, personality displaying itself in the
form of personality É beyond this art cannot go."[5]
Forty years later in Art and Experience Dewey returns to the idea of ranking the arts, but by then
his views had changed. He presents the very fact that Schopenhauer even thought
to rank the arts as evidence of "a complete failure of philosophy to meet the
challenge that art offers reflective thought."[6]
By 1931 Dewey is no longer willing to give any art form pride of place among
the arts.
The
question I want to take up is the place of poetry in the arts: specifically
does it hold pride of place either as the telos of art, or the essence of art,
or at least as deserving special consideration among the arts. I will look at Dewey's
theory of poetry and how he argues that it does not hold a philosophically
distinctive place and contrast it with Hans-Georg Gadamer's theory about "the
essential priority of poetry with respect to the other arts."[7]
Martin Heidegger may have expressed the view most dramatically when he claimed
that "the essence of art is poetry"[8]
but, as in so many other cases, it is Gadamer who fully articulates it and
locates it in the history of philosophy. Finally I will argue with Gadamer that
poetry does have a distinctive place among the arts, and poetry is particularly
useful for helping us understand the arts in general. The key to this argument
is seeing that language, especially poetic language, is not first a foremost a
tool, not even, as Dewey writes, the "tool of tools."[9]
I.
Dewey's Understanding of Poetry among the Arts
Of course what Dewey is known most for is arguing against
distinguishing art from other areas of life. In Art as Experience it is the continuity among the arts, and above all the
continuity of aesthetic experience and everyday experience, that takes the
fore. He argues that were we to understand life as
practical through and through, as we should, "then would disappear the
separations that trouble present thinking: division of everything into nature and experience, of experience in practice and theory, art and
science, or art into useful and fine,
menial and free."[10]
Poetry can be analyzed separately from the other arts, but for the Dewey of Art
and Experience is holds no special status
among the arts. His emphasis is always on the connections between all the arts
and experience.
Dewey sees the distinction
between fine art and useful art as falling away once we realize the common
anthropological roots of the two categories. The role of fine art always arises
within the practical needs of life; it does not transcend them. All arts
develop in order to emotionally mark significant objects or experiences to
enable them to be better communicated across people and over time. Therefore,
with respect to poetry, Dewey says "words serve their poetic purpose in the degree
in which they summon and evoke into active operation the vital responses that
are present whenever we experience qualities."[11] The qualities of an
experience are those that provide the unity to the experience; poetry becomes a
way to communicate these qualities, in the process generating an experience. As
a result poetry brings to attention features of the experience that may be
particularly useful for our ongoing adaptation to our environment. It is "the
emotional kindling of reality, which is the true province of poetry;"[12] poetry "radiates the light
that never was on land and sea but that henceforth is an abiding illumination
of objects."[13] Of course this same
illuminating and attention-grabbing function might be played by prose as well
as poetry; the difference between the two is that:
One of them [prose] realizes the power of words to express what
is in heaven and earth and under the seas by means of extension; the other
[poetry] by intension. The prosaic is an affair of description and narration,
of details accumulated and relations elaborated. It spreads as it goes like a
legal document or catalogue. The poetic reverses the process. It condenses and
abbreviates, thus giving words an energy of expansion that is almost explosive.[14]
It is its energy—especially its spontaneous
energy—that gives poetry its significant character as art and
distinguishes it from prose, but for Dewey it shares that energy with other
performance arts: dance, theater and music.
What Dewey seeks to avoid are
two extremes: that poetry is straightforwardly referential and that poetry is
wholly unrelated to truth. Poetry,
as art, "communicates because it is expressive" not because it is linguistic.
It enables us to share vividly and deeply in meanings to which
we had been dumb, or for which we had but the ear that permits what is said to
pass through in transit to overt action. For communication is not announcing
things, even if they are said with the emphasis of great sonority.
Communication is the process of creating participation, of making common what
had been isolated and singular; and part of the miracle it achieves is that, in
being communicated, the conveyance of meaning gives body and definiteness to the
experience of the one who utters as well as to that of those who listen.[15]
The emotional qualities of the poem, not the referential
properties of the words, create an experience for the reader or listener.
Still, Dewey's is not a purely non-cognitive account of poetry and art. It is
not simply that poetry has its domain of emotions and metaphors, while science
and inquiry have their domain of truth. The emotional quality of a poem
communicates an experience of an idea or a thing—it communicates the same
world that science and inquiry communicates, otherwise poetry could not connect
to action.
In his early more Hegelian
phase he wrote, "The great power of poetry to stay and to console—a power
which neither [Matthew] Arnold nor any other critic can exaggerate one
whit—is just because of the truth, the rendering of the reality of
affairs, which poetry gives us. The importance and the endurance of poetry, as
of all art, [is] in its hold upon reality."[16] As experience is always at
the same time emotional and intellectual, often undifferentiably so, its
content is never merely a subjective reaction, but an active interaction with
our environment revealing things about our environment in the process.
[E]sthetic and moral experience reveal traits of real things as
truly as does intellectual experience, that poetry may have a metaphysical
import as well as science, is rarely affirmed, and when it is asserted, the
statement is likely to be meant in some mystical or esoteric sense rather than
in a straightforward everyday sense.[17]
For Dewey, poetry straightforwardly "reveal[s] traits of real
things." What makes a poem powerful as a work of art may be its emotional
quality, but this is not at the expense of generating insights for inquiry;
still it reveals in a different way than do science or philosophy. Dewey writes: "if the advantage in
directness and universality of appeal, in wealth and passionateness of garb, is
upon the side of poetry, let us remember that, after all, the advantage upon
the side of method and standard are with the side of science and philosophy."[18] Poetry may be able to speak
with greater passion and greater universality, but it in the end its appeal as
art is emotional—in this way Dewey can bridge the dichotomy between
poetry functioning purely intellectually and poetry functioning purely
emotionally.[19]
For
all this about poetry, we really haven't gone beyond what Dewey says about art
in general. At the heart of Dewey's aesthetic theory is "recovering the continuity of aesthetic
experience with normal processes of living."[20] All art is created with the goal of
generating a single coherent aesthetic experience and all aesthetic experience
includes intellectual, emotional and practical elements—art generates
insights for inquiry, communicates emotions, and guides interaction with our
environment. In Art and Experience
Dewey is blunt about his focus on the continuity of aesthetic forms and his
disdain for distinctions among the arts. He writes,
William James remarked on the tediousness of elaborate classifications
of things that merge and vary, as do human emotions. Attempts at precise and
systematic classification of fine arts seem to me to share this tediousness. An
enumerative classification is convenient and for purposes of easy reference
indispensable. But a cataloguing like painting, statuary, poetry, drama,
dancing, landscape gardening, architecture, singing, musical instrumentation,
etc., etc., makes no pretense to throwing any light on the intrinsic nature of
the things listed. It leaves that illumination to come from the only place that
it can come from—individual works of art. Rigid classifications are inept
(if they are taken seriously) because they distract attention from that which
is esthetically basic—the qualitatively unique and integral character of
experience of an art product.[21]
Distinctions
are only useful to the extent they draw our attention to what is aesthetically
relevant in the experience of a work of art; but what is most relevant is that
"art, in its form, unites the very same relation of doing and undergoing,
outgoing and incoming energy, that makes an experience be an experience."[22]
So although there are differences between poetry and other arts, they are not
differences that make a difference, and no art form assumes an elevated status
about others. Poetry is neither the telos of art, nor the essence of art, not
even exemplary among the arts.
II.
Gadamer's Elevation of Poetry among the Arts.
Gadamer
regularly claims that the distinctive feature of poetry is its autonomy. By this
he means that poems "interpret themselves insofar as one need no additional
information about the occasion and the historical circumstances of their
composition."[23] Gadamer is not denying that our
interpretation of a poem does not draw on our particular cultural, historical,
and personal backgrounds—all interpretation is shaped by our facticity;
indeed for Gadamer it is only because we are finite that poems can become
intelligible—rather the claim of autonomy connects three related ideas.
First, poetry, like all language and all art, transcends the context of its
origins. When we put our thoughts into words, we make open the possibility the
meaningfulness of the words will outlast us and our thoughts. Unlike most
prose, though, a poem stands alone as a unitary object to be interpreted in its
uniqueness. Any additional information about the author or the context of its
creation are only legitimate tools of interpretation to the extent the poem
itself bears that interpretation; but even then, additional information only
provides mere clues to the ideality of the poem, it never constitutes the
poem's meaning. That the meaning of the poem is not reducible to the intentions
of the poet is the second feature of autonomy, for Gadamer. The third is that
the poem speaks for itself; the meaning of a poem will not be captured in
prose, in other poems, or even, as someone might suggest, through other
artistic mediums. The poem is the best expression of its meaning, and no
interpretation will exhaust what it has to say. One way to think of Gadamer's
autonomy claim is as a three-fold denial of irreducibility: the meaning of the
work of art is not reducible to its historical and cultural origin, to its
creator's intentions, nor to expression in another medium, including prose.
One
extremely significant consequence of the autonomy of poetry is that, for
Gadamer and in contrast to Dewey, poetry is not first and foremost a kind of
communication. Dewey argues that a poem is successful if there is a connection
between the emotions of the artist and the emotions of the reader; at its
heart, then, the poem functions as a medium for emotional communication. For
Gadamer the poem stands on its own; its meaning is its own, rather than it
being a vehicle for its author's meaning. As he puts it, poetry doesn't report,
it testifies; it stands on its words.[24]
To
flesh out the meaning of poetry's autonomy Gadamer appropriates Paul ValŽry's
currency metaphor. Everyday prose is like paper money: it is purely symbolic
and its value comes from its ability to be substituted and exchanged for
objects. Poetry is like a gold coin, useful for exchange of course, but
valuable in its own right, even after the images on the coin marking it as
currency have worn off.
[Everyday] language never stands for itself. It stands for
something we encounter in the practical activities of life or in scientific
experience, and it is in this context that the views we express prove
themselves of fail to do so. Words do not Ôstand' on their own account. Whether
they are spoken or written, their meaning is only fully realized in the context
of life. ValŽry contrasted the poetic word with the everyday use of language in
a striking comparison that alludes to the old days of the gold standard:
everyday language resembles small change which, like our paper money does not
actually posses the value it symbolizes.
The famous gold coins used before the First World War, on the other
hand, actually possessed as metal the value
that was imprinted upon them. In a similar way the language of poetry is not a
mere pointer that refers to something else, but, like the gold coin, is what it
represents.[25]
Gadamer's
point here is that in poetry the words have an intrinsic value that doesn't
vanish in their meaning. Poetry does not lose its textual presence in revealing
what it reveals. Whatever insights we may gain from a poem, the poetic words
retain their power to reveal and also show the potential for further
interpretations. We recognize when reading a poem that it is these words, these
sounds, that are producing the effect, and unless the poem is particularly
mundane, it is only because of these words that the poem has the effect it has.
That the meaning of a poem doesn't leave the words behind is part of its
autonomy. Along the same lines, Gadamer points out that no poems are every
really translated. What happens instead is new poems are written in a new
language that tries to capture the power and meaning of the original
poem—this is why the best translators of poems are poets themselves.
However, the translation is always a separate poem, autonomous as well.
Finally,
to add to Gadamer's account of poetry as autonomous, consider what we do when
we interpret a work of art. We seek to make the meaning explicit by finding
words that best express what the work expresses. We try to match the subject
matter as revealed by the work of art with the subject matter as revealed by
our own words—we don't expect perfect success in this project, but we
don't let our limitations leave us inarticulate either. In poetry this
situation is changed slightly, but significantly. We already have words
expressing the subject matter of the work—the poem itself—and we
seek new words to express the subject matter in the same way. The activity of
interpreting a poem is not one of becoming articulate about what is expressed
by the poem, but of translating the meaning of the poem into prose. But no
translation of the meaning of the poem could express the meaning as well as the
poem—the best expression in language of the meaning of the poem is the
poem itself. So the process of interpreting a poem is not one of finding new
words to express the poem's meaning, but finding our way into the meaning of
the poem's own words. The words of the poem are irreplaceable in an interpretation;
this is the core meaning of Gadamer's claim that poetry is autonomous, and its
status as such gives it an "essential priority" with respect to other art
forms.
III.
Poetic Language
I
think Gadamer is right that poetry deserves special consideration among the
arts. I am not going to engage in or endorse the project of ranking the arts,
but I do believe that thinking about the uniqueness of poetry helps us to
understand general truths about the arts. Something like this is Gadamer's view
as well. Let me start by pointing out that both Dewey and Gadamer are
"response" theorists in philosophy of art. When discussing what makes art
significant, both emphasize the way the work of art is received by the viewer,
hearer, or reader. It is in the effects of art that art gets its distinctive
character, even if those effects themselves are continuous with other areas of
our lives. Artworks are understood not first and foremost in terms of being the
outcome of creative acts, nor as being intended to be perceived in a certain
way, nor as having certain formal properties, nor as having an appropriate
relation to the art world, but as being capable of creating an effect on or
with an appreciator—an effect not found in interaction with commonplace
objects.[26] In Dewey's case this effect is an
experience; in Gadamer's case it is the event of truth, but in both cases the
effects are what is relevant.
In addition, Dewey and Gadamer share a
naturalistic approach to art; that is, they see art as arising out of our
nature and as continuous with our nature.
In Experience and Nature
Dewey writes
There are substantially but two alternatives. Either art is a
continuation, by means of intelligent selection and arrangement, of natural
tendencies of natural events; or art is a peculiar addition to nature springing
from something dwelling exclusively within the breast of man, whatever name be
given the latter. In the former case, delightfully enhanced perception or
esthetic appreciation is of the same nature as enjoyment of any object that is
consummatory. It is the outcome of a skilled and intelligent art of dealing
with natural things for the sake of intensifying, purifying, prolonging and
deepening the satisfactions which they spontaneously afford.[27]
Gadamer too thinks that art is "a continuation É of natural
tendencies of natural events"; the play that reveals truth in the presence of a
work of art is but a specific example of the play that models all interaction,
and especially dialogical interaction.
The difference between the Dewey
and Gadamer ultimately falls on the question of the relation between language and experience.[28]
On the one hand, their conceptions of language have much in common. Both hold
that language is essentially related to conversation, and, as such, both would
reject the idea there could be a private language; also both see reflection as
an activity that is derivative of, and parallel to, communication with others.
We can reflect in words because we can talk to others in words. Both therefore
see language as a tool not only of communication, but also of thought. Language
allows us to keep things present to consciousness even in the thing's absence,
and relations among words help us to better understand possible relations among
things. On the other hand, they disagree on language's status as a
tool—the "tool of tools" in Dewey's words.[29] Dewey grants language special status
among tools, yet it is never anything other than a tool. Gadamer joins
Heidegger in arguing that although we can and do use language, the mode of
being of language is not ready-to-handness; language is not essentially a tool.
Heidegger calls it the house of being and says we "inhabit" language; Gadamer,
not to be out-metaphored, says our relation to language is like a fish's
relation to water. We live and in through language and it is our relation to
language that makes it useful as a tool; language's usefulness is derived from
its connection to our nature—our "linguisticality."[30]
Metaphors aside, the primary function of
language, according to Gadamer, is disclosure. A central idea of hermeneutic
phenomenology is that phenomena do not first disclose themselves to a subject,
only then to be described, but are disclosed through the use of language.
Language always furnishes the fundamental articulations that
guide our understanding of the world. It belongs to the nature of familiarity
with the world that whenever we exchange words with one another, we share the
world. É Language gives all of us our access to a world in which certain
special forms of human experience arise: the religious tidings that proclaim
salvation, the legal judgment that tells us what is right and what is wrong in
our society, the poetic word that by being there bears witness to our own
being.[31]
Working
with someone to become articulate about a subject matter—Gadamer's
definition of dialogue—is the means by which phenomena become conscious.
We articulate things in words and come to understand them in the process.
Because language is a medium of shared disclosure it is a medium for
communication.
Compare the difference between Dewey and
Gadamer on the tool-nature of language with their views on the usefulness of
one's hands—an example dear to both Gadamer and Dewey.[32] Clearly, hands are very useful tools. We
do things with them constantly, and were we to lose them—or lose our
ability to use them—we'd have to go to great lengths to compensate for
the lost functionality. But our hands are not just tools; they are a way in
which the world shows itself to us. Not only can we feel and touch things we
might not be able to see and not only can properties be disclosed to touch in
ways they might not be disclosed to other senses—two obvious ways in
which hands might be disclosive—but our hands are integrated with our
other senses to guide their disclosive ability. We perceive our environment in
the way we do because we have hands with certain functions. Perhaps the
clearest presentation of this is by Dewey himself in his "Reflex Arc" essay:
[T]he ability of the hand to do its work will depend, either
directly or indirectly, upon its control, as well as its stimulation, by the
act of vision. If the sight did not inhibit as well as excite the reaching, the
latter would be purely indeterminate, it would be for anything or nothing, not
for the particular object seen. The reaching, in turn, must both stimulate and
control the seeing. The eye must be kept upon the candle if the arm is to do
its work; let it wander and the arm takes up another task. In other words, we
now have an enlarged and transformed co-ordination; the act is seeing no less
than before, but it is now seeing-for-reaching purposes. [33]
Although
Dewey tends to constrain all attention to occasions of inquiry, for Gadamer the
phenomenologist, the at-hand character of experience is ubiquitous, in which
case hands are not just tools. They form an essential way the world is
disclosed to us. Things reveal themselves to us as something to grasp, or to
reach for, or as lying within or beyond reach, and it is not a coincidence that
"grasping" something is synonymous with understanding something. Hands are
useful as tools in virtue of the more fundamental fact that hands disclose.
Language,
for Gadamer is disclosive of reality in just the same way. Just as things
reveal themselves to us the way they do in virtue of our bodily comportment to
them, things reveal themselves to as something or other, and this as-structure
of perception is linguistically informed. We see something as a kind of thing
because we have words to make sense of it as something. Things disclose
themselves to us as objects of conceptual understanding, or as calling for
articulation and description, which is to say disclosed as informed by
language. This is the sense in which language functions in experience for
Gadamer.
It is a short step from the
linguisticality of experience to the Gadamerian view that "language performs
thought," that the criteria for successful thinking are the criteria for
successful use of language. So while Dewey sees language as wholly
instrumental, Gadamer sees it as instrumental in virtue of its disclosive
power—that difference marks out the differences between their aesthetic
theories and their theories of poetry.[34] For Gadamer, poetry has a special status
because language has this distinctive role to play in experience. For the most part, we are not aware of
the ways in which language is functioning in experience as disclosive; poetry
however, wears its character as disclosive language on its sleeve. It shows language
at work—in the process of disclosing—and it is in this sense that
Gadamer calls poetry "the highest fulfillment of that revealing which is the
achievement of speech."[35]
All art connects to experience; because of the distinctively linguistic
character of experience, the art of poetry does this most directly and
perspicuously.
Moreover, while all aesthetic experience
is interactive, poetry reveals this most clearly since reading poetry is always
a performative event. As a reader we are in a position analogous to the
musician or the dancer—we are generating the aesthetic experience as well
as undergoing it. Since interpreting the work converges with performing it, we
can vary the performance—pausing at different points, emphasizing
different sounds—in the process varying the interpretation. Now it may be
that all art appreciation and interpretation is performative in a similar way;
my point here is that in poetry this fact is most clearly realized, and, as
such, it places poetry in a privileged position with respect to the other arts.
Poetry serves an exemplary role for understanding the nature of art.
Often the small differences are the most illuminating ones. Dewey's and Gadamer's theories of art share much in common; they
disagree, however, on the classic question of how the arts should be ranked,
or, in Dewey's case, whether they should be ranked at all. It turns out that
behind the disagreement lies a significant difference as to how they see our
relationship to language, and this difference leads them to competing theories
of poetry. Siding with Gadamer that language is not merely a tool, but a fundamental
way in which the world is disclosed to us, I think Gadamer is right that poetry
both holds pride of place among the arts and is exemplary of the disclosive
power of all language. "In words we are at homeÉ.especially in the poetic
use of language is this clear to all of us." [36]
David
Vessey
University
of Chicago
[1] Hegel's Introduction to Aesthetics, translated by T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 89.
[2] World as Will and Representation, Vol. I (New York: Dover, 1966), 320.
[3] World as Will and Representation, Vol. II (New York: Dover, 1966), 448.
[4] Early Works of John Dewey, Vol. 2, 1887: Psychology (Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois University Press, 1970), 274. Hereafter citations of Dewey's quotations will be given by the abbreviation EW for Early Works, MW for Middle Works, and LW for Later Works, followed by the volume number and the page number—for example, EW.2.274.
[5] EW.2.277.
[6] LW.10.295.
[7] "Poetry and
Mimesis" in The Relevance of the Beautiful and Other Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 117. Contrasts between Dewey and Gadamer's
work are becoming more prominent in the literature. On just the topic of
philosophy of art there are Thomas Jeannot's "A Propaedeutic to the
Philosophical Hermeneutics of John Dewey: Art as Experience and Truth and Method"
and Robert Innis's "Perception, Interpretation, and the Signs of Art" both in The
Journal of Speculative Philosophy,
15/1 (2001), Richard Shusterman's "The End of Aesthetic Experience" in Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 55/1 (1997), John Gilmour's "Dewey and
Gadamer on the Ontology of Art" in Man and World, 20 (1987), Joaquin Zuniga's "An
Everyday Aesthetic Impulse: Dewey Revisited" in British Journal of
Aesthetics, 29 (1989),
and Thomas Alexander's "Eros and Understanding: Gadamer's Aesthetic Ontology of
the Community" in The Philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer, edited by Louis Hahn (Chicago: Open
Court, 1997).
[8] "The Origin of the Work of Art" Basic Writings, edited by David Farrell Krell (San Francisco: Harper Collins,1993), 199.
[9] LW.1.134.
[10] LW.1.269.
[11] LW.10.220.
[12] EW.3.112.
[13] LW.1.270.
[14] LW.10.246.
[15] LW.10.248.
[16] EW.3.122. Compare: "I cannot rid myself of the conviction that the weight and the humanity of the message of the poet are proportionate to the weighty and human ideas which he develops; that these ideas must be capable of verification to the intelligence—must be true in that system of knowledge which is science, in that discussion of the meaning of experience which is philosophy" (EW.3.119).
[17] LW.1.27.
[18] EW.3.123.
[19] Music was often given credit for appealing the more directly and most broadly as music is unmediated by ideas and Dewey does give music credit for being able to take something otherwise un-malleable and give it rhythmic and melodic meaning. "There are critics who hold that music outrivals poetry in its power to convey a sense of life and phases of life as we should desire them to be. I cannot, however, but think that by the very nature of its medium music is brutally organic: not, of course, in the sense in which Ôbrutal' signifies Ôbeastly,' but as we speak of brute facts, of that which is undeniable and unescapable, because so inevitably there. Nor is this view disparaging to music. Its value is precisely that it can take material which is organically assertive and apparently intractable, and make melody and harmony out of it" (LW.10.247).
[20] LW.10.16.
[21] LW.10.221.
[22] LW.10.54.
[23] "Religious and Poetical Speech" in Myth, Symbol and Reality, edited by Alan Olson and Leroy Rouner (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1980), 86.
[24] "The common aspect in all literature, however, lies obviously in the fact that the writer himself disappears because he has given to the linguistic form such an ideal form that nothing can be added. Everything is in the words of the text exactly as they appear in the text. We call that the art of writing" ("Philosophy and Literature" in Man and World 18(2): 1985, 249).
[25] "Philosophy and Poetry" in The Relevance of the Beautiful, 132–33, emphasis his.
[26] It is no coincidence that Louise Rosenblatt, the American founder of the reception theory of reading, was a Deweyean—see her The Reader, The Text, The Poem (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1978)—and that Hans-Robert Jauss, the main German proponent of reception theory, did his dissertation under Gadamer—see his Toward an Aesthetic of Reception, translated by Timothy Bahti (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982).
[27] LW.1.291. He goes on to reject the second alternative.
[28] Heidegger had something like this in mind when he wrote
The linguistic work, poetry in the
narrower sense, has a privileged position among the arts as a whole. To see
this all me need is the right concept of language. According to the usual
account, language is a kind of communication. It serves as a means of
discussion and agreement, in general for achieving understanding. But language
is neither merely nor primarily the aural and written expression of what needs
to be communicated. The conveying of overt and covert meanings is not what
language, in the first instance, does. Rather, it brings beings as beings, for
the first time, into the open" (46–47, "The Origin of the Work of Art,"
in Off the Beaten Track, edited and
translated by Julian Young and Kenneth Haynes [Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2002]).
[29] LW.1.134.
[30] For Gadamer's account of linguisticality see especially his "Towards a Phenomenology of Ritual and Language" in Language and Linguisticality in Gadamer's Hermeneutics, edited by Lawrence Schmidt (Lanham, Md.: Lexington Books, 2000), 19-50.
[31] "Philosophical Foundations of the Twentieth-Century" in Philosophical Hermeneutics, translated by David Linge (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976), 115.
[32] Gadamer writes, "[b]ecause the body presents itself as something with which we are intimate and not like an obstacle, it is precisely what sets us free and lets us be open for what is." (p. 30, "Praise of Theory" in Praise of Theory: Speeches and Essays, translated by Chris Dawson [New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998]).
[33] EW.5.98.
[34] A version of this argument is made by Bill Blattner in "The Primacy of Practice and Assertoric Truth: Dewey and Heidegger" in Heidegger, Authenticity and Modernity: Essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, vol. 1, edited by Mark Wrathall and Jeffrey Malpas (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2000), 231-249.
[35] "On the Contribution of Poetry to the Search for Truth," in Relevance of the Beautiful, 112.
[36] "Language and Understanding" in Theory,
Culture & Society 23/1 (2006),
26.